Further Thoughts on Aristotle’s Politics

Aristotle’s treatise on politics is the essential work on political philosophy from classical antiquity. Since the death of Socrates, philosophy had to learn to conceal itself from the wayward opinions of the majority. People are biased and occasionally these biases are directed at people in an unenlightened way. Each age and political regime carries certain prejudices, but philosophy’s goal is to rise above particular prejudices in an effort to examine the nature of things -and this is a dangerous project to political life. Free inquiry is antithetical to the essentially religious nature of politics. In the ancient world there was no such thing as freedom of speech nor freedom of religion and so on. Thus, Socrates was condemned to die for impiety as well as for spreading his allegedly idle tricks to the youth of Athens. Therefore in an effort to continue the exploration of the best political regime (i.e. the pursuit of justice) philosophers are compelled to disguise their true convictions. Plato conceals himself behind a mask of poetry in dialogic form, while Aristotle takes another approach. We know Aristotle wrote some dialogues in his day, but what comes down are Aristotle’s extensive treatises.

In many of his treatises, Aristotle begins his texts by making large, declarative statements that generally reflect the established opinions of his day, but as the book proceeds, we soon discover that Aristotle has examined and broken apart those common opinions so that we may rise above what is common to see things from a higher perspective. And that is exactly what he does in his masterpiece, the Politics.

Book I of Aristotle’s Politics is devoted to distinguishing two different kinds of rule (which other writers confuse -presumably Plato and Xenophon), however the true meat of the text begins with a ‘new founding’ in Book III wherein the parts of the city are discussed, namely the citizens, as well as the four cardinal virtues (courage, moderation, prudence, and justice). Each of the cardinal virtues arise in Aristotle’s discussion of how to properly govern a household: not according to property, but rather according to virtue. At the outset, he claims that the best way to approach an examination of justice is to first examine

For Aristotle, the city is the highest expression of man’s political potential -it is small and distinct from a nation (ethnos) and further still from an empire. Perhaps most importantly, a city has limits. Readers of Aristotle cannot help but wonder what Aristotle would think of the nation state. Given his preference for a small, self-sufficient community which is in pursuit of virtue, Aristotle would likely find the modern nation state to be a hideous monstrosity. He follows from Plato’s lead in the Republic by analyzing the character of each regime (i.e. democracy, oligarchy, monarchy, republicanism and so on), though his preference comes to light for the rule of the ‘best of men’ -an aristocracy, or perhaps we might call it an aristocratic republic.

Curiously, in Aristotle the city is a naturally occurring organism for mankind because ‘man is a political animal,’ yet the city is also founded intentionally. The city does not occur automatically in the same way that herds of animals organize themselves. A city is founded on a vision of the good, on the idea of justice. Without the pursuit of justice, humans fall into hideous abuses because most of politics is about preventing the bad rather than pursuing the good. Aristotle does not hold an ‘optimistic’ view of human potential. The city, or any political association for that matter, arises out of several needs and desires: such as for humans to share with one another, for humans to derive meaning and purpose from their collective, and also out of a need for security and mutual benefit (which later becomes the primary justification for the modern political community from the so-called “state of nature” writers like Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau). The human political community begins as a naturally paternalistic embryo: it begins with the family, or the household. A family is ruled by two parents (contra popular opinion, Aristotle exoterically critiques the idea of full equality between men and women, while esoterically he cites ‘the poets’ with a quote from Sophocles’s Ajax in which Ajax goes mad while his wife attempts to reason with him).

At any rate, for Aristotle the household relies on slavery -a kind of natural slave who is deficient intellectually. He accepts a natural hierarchy among beings -some are better suited to lead, some are better suited to follow. A slave is someone incapable of ruling himself for Aristotle. The notion of ancient natural hierarchies is foreign to the modern mind as productive machinery and the firm belief in democratic values has overcome the desire for hierarchical order (this optimism has soured into skepticism in our present day).

The chief insight we gain in reading Book III of Aristotle’s Politics is an awareness of the immense complexity in determining the city in motion. A city, or politics, is rife with inconsistencies and tensions. Who speaks for the city -the revolutionaries? The leaders? How shall we characterize an existing regime? Who belongs to the city? Who is a citizen? Aristotle suggests the citizen is one who truly and fully engages in the decision-making and office of the city. Each citizen pursues his own interests, the rule of his household, while also seeking for the common good. Similarly each competing regime (i.e. democracy, oligarchy, monarchy, aristocracy and so on) believes it is pursuing the common good. Every regime claims to be just. Perhaps in some ways like Herodotus, Aristotle begins by posing a fundamental question about political life, he then answers that question with common opinions, and then puzzles the reader by presenting other conflicting common opinions. Dialectically, the conflict or disagreement leads the reader to a higher perspective regarding the problematic nature of politics.

At any rate, returning briefly to the inquiry about citizenry, Aristotle asks who the truly fulfilled citizen is: he discusses the democrat, the oligarch and so on. Ultimately, Aristotle suggests a certain level of praise for the remote contemplative life -the philosophic life. He offers a certain praise that is consistent with the Jeffersonian ideal -a rural republic of farmers who pursue an honorable life and the offices of governance are not desirable because the offices do not offer financial incentives. Active engagement in political life is not necessarily preferable for Aristotle: a life of leisure (the word leisure here means something akin to serious intellectual work, coupled with laborious daily work for business or personal reasons -it is different from idle oligarchs or overworked peasants). The Politics comes to light as a book that inspires politically inquisitive minds in all places and times: it is a trans-civic work of inspiration and inquiry.


This essay was heavily influenced by Thomas Pangle and Timothy Burns and their writings on “Aristotle’s Politics” in their book The Key Texts of Political Philosophy.

Political Theology in the Bible: An Exegesis

In the Bible, an infinitely distant God creates the world and then places humans inside it. He is an artisan and a poet –He speaks life into existence. However, the account of His creation was not witnessed by any living human, yet curiously an anonymous narrator shares the story through revealed scripture (tradition holds this narrator to be Moses). How is this possible? To proceed we must accept its validity in theory. God’s initial intent for humans is that they be immortal yet blissfully ignorant denizens of the Garden of Eden, however the humans immediately disobey the law laid down by God which is not to eat the fruit of the Tree of Knowledge of Good and Evil. Initially, humans are unsatisfied to live according to mere need (as Marx might proffer) nor by pure hedonistic self-interest (as Utilitarians like Jeremy Bentham or Adam Smith might claim). This dissatisfaction with extremes points to a human desire to gain knowledge of things, particular moral knowledge of good and evil –ancient Greek might suggest it is an Aristotelian example of stretching out toward knowledge. After the humans disobey God, their eyes become opened, mirroring exactly what the cunning serpent suggested. Upon learning of their transgression, God banishes the humans –along with their new knowledge from the Garden of Eden– never to return again. Paradise is lost for humanity owing to the failings of its predecessors. Meanwhile, God remains disappointed and resentful of the humans and their disobedient desire for knowledge. As further evidence of this, God punishes future human offspring: Cain is punished for killing his brother Abel out of jealousy. Abel is a shepherd and a nomad, and God approves of his sacrifice; whereas Cain is a settled farmer who works the land and whose seed beholds future creators –musicians, builders of cities, and other human crafts. However, the human genealogy of the other brother, Seth (born after Abel’s murder), is what carries the human race through Noah. These humans are mainly a people who “walk with God” (Genesis 5:24). Like Abel, God prefers humans to have an unsettled, uncomfortable, and nomadic life. God is skeptical of cities, human greatness, autonomy, and the pursuit of knowledge. After all, the Bible calls for “righteousness” rather than “civilization.”

However, as time passes mankind grows wicked. There are no laws and humans live in freedom. They possess the knowledge that they will one day die (perhaps not unlike Gilgamesh) and this soon causes them to rebel, so God endeavors to destroy life through a catastrophic flood, saving only Noah and his family (descendants of Seth). When Noah emerges from the receding floodwaters and sacrifices, God finally acknowledges man’s “evil” nature and he makes a concession –a promise never to destroy innocent life again. Notably, with the flood, God performs a similar act in response to Cain’s earlier sin: namely the act of murder. God has no moral qualms about murder in these early sections of the Hebrew Bible. At any rate, God is learning how best to handle human beings –there is an extraordinary dialectic unfolding in Genesis and Exodus between man and God.

Noah becomes the first man to grow a vineyard and one day he drinks in excess while his son Ham transgresses an unspoken law –seeing his father’s nakedness. Ham (the future father of Canaan) is cursed while Noah’s other two sons are praised. From this point onward, humanity becomes divided into the “cursed” and the “blessed.” In addition, the descendants of Noah under Nimrod build the mighty tower of Babel in order to penetrate the heavens where God dwells and also to make a name for themselves as one people, until God ‘comes down’ and thwarts human efforts toward self-reliance, pride, and techne. He confuses languages and scatters humans in different nations across the earth. There is presumably something dangerous or threatening to God’s authority if humans live according to one single city or state.

Next, God –ceaselessly disappointed in humanity’ recalcitrance– chooses to elevate one nation as his “chosen people” under the fatherhood of Abraham. Who is Abraham and why would God choose him? What characterizes Abraham as important? For starters, he circumcises himself and his household as a sign of his devotion to God, but more importantly, there are three chief passages that demonstrate Abraham’s increasing awareness of his own mortality, as well as a deeper faith in and a love for God. First, in his old age Abraham has a son named Isaac (meaning “he will laugh” –because of the way Abraham laughs at the thought of a child, though not in a contemptuous way because that form of laughter would presuppose a distinction between things that are possible and impossible). At any rate, God seemingly breaks his own covenant formed with Noah when he commands Abraham to sacrifice his son as a show of true obedience and child-like love for God without qualification. However, at the last moment God rescues Isaac. Only by accepting God as wholly unfathomable, yet also perfectly just, can a person come to be rewarded by God. Thus the Bible preserves the classical idea of self-sacrificial love: a Biblical hero is one who commits wholly to God’s unfathomable demands. Indeed, throughout the Bible, humans are blamed for their own failings, but God claims all the glory for their accomplishments.

Next, we follow the descendants of Isaac, particularly Jacob or “Israel” –the patriarch of the future nation, and his son Joseph’s rise through slavery in Egypt to become Pharaoh. The pure despotism of the Egyptian government is contrasted with the simple, nomadic life of the burgeoning Israelites. As time passes, the rule of Joseph is forgotten and the Israelites become an enslaved people with no proud leaders of their own anymore, nor any experience in ruling themselves, until Moses rises up to lead the people (i.e. God’s people, not Moses’s people). He leads them out of Egypt and to the promised land. In the books of Leviticus, Numbers, and Deuteronomy, we are provided with a vast array of laws handed down to Moses who delivers them to the wayward, wandering people of God. Unlike the works of political philosophy found in the writings of Athens, there is no explicit teaching of the “best regime” in the Bible. Instead, we are offered a glimpse into the theocratic teachings of ancient Israel, most of which are prohibitive injunctions.

The closest example we find in the Bible to a political teaching is through the narrative of an exemplary, chosen people which wrestles with its own political existence as a series of successive systems of authority unfold. Only through a painful and purifying process can humans hope to live up to their nature –made of mere dust, yet also created in the image of God. This process requires the search for the “best regime” for humanity (which now possesses a certain divine intelligence).

The first regime to appear in the narrative is the patriarchal regime, best exemplified in the story of Abraham, but this regime proves faulty as the sons of Jacob and their tribal offspring can hardly keep peace among themselves. What is needed is the rule of law –divine law– but in the second regime we gain a glimpse of the pure despotism of the Pharaonic regime in Egypt, completed by Joseph when he abolishes all private property in Egypt. The Egyptians are a nation who have mastered control over their environment (such as irrigation canals from the Nile) and thus they do not require dependence on the whims of the natural world. They are an irreligious people, as well, though they do praise the power of human magic. Pharaoh embodies the desires of Nimrod and his construction of the Tower of Babel. A higher power embodies the necessary constraints on this kind of regime.

The third political order is the Moses as liberator from Pharaoh and in pursuit of divine law. After wandering into the desert, the laws are handed down at Sinai. These laws are intrinsic and they do not rely on any modern notion of the ‘consent of the governed.’ In delivering these holy laws, God further continues His quest toward becoming ruler of humans, and His authority is absolute. According to the law, the economic sphere protects a certain degree of private property –fraternity and charity is not merely encouraged but rather enforced– and in the erotic sphere, sexual pleasure is allowed only insofar as it serves the perpetuation of the patriarchal lineage. Lastly, the principle of retribution reigns supreme over the penal code of ancient Israel. Nowhere is the distinction between Jerusalem and Athens more apparent than in the Mosaic laws which are contrary to Plato’s Laws and the oft-repeated Socratic assertion that virtue is knowledge, and vice ignorance. Mosaic law details injunctions in order to instill a “pure” and holy people, but the laws are unclear on the future of the regime (i.e. political succession), or how the laws will be enforced.

In the fourth regime, we encounter Joshua, the conquering warlord who rules the Israelites with a zeal for exterminating surrounding tribes. However, following the rulership of Joshua comes the problematic rule of Judges –a reign characterized by chaos and a tribal confederacy that is mired in near constant disagreement. However, scripture seems to indicate that God favors this reign of the Judges, a political quagmire wherein humans are fragile, vulnerable, and internally chaotic.

Lastly, we see the sixth and final political regime offered in the Hebrew Bible: a divinely anointed monarchy. The kingship begins with a demand from the people that they become a ‘nation like other nations’ and so the tallest man, an all-too-human man named Saul is chosen by lot but he is soon proven to be an insufficient leader. The monarchy has allowed Israel to rise to new cultural heights, only to devolve into despotism, as with the Pharaohs in Genesis and Exodus. Saul is initially brought to the kingship against the wishes of the prophet Samuel, as well as in opposition to God who allows the Israelites to experience a human king only insofar as it may show them how corrupt and evil a human ruler can be, however the Judges are the most stark symbols of corruption. In contrast, Saul is a dependable king by all measures. His chief flaw is that he governs humans in their own interests and he does not obey the commandment of God when God instructs the Israelites to offer up everything as an offering to God during one of their conquests of the Philistines, however Saul instructs his people them to keep what is good and offer the rest to God. Mankind is deserving of what is good, whereas God is owed the rest.

At any rate, the kingship is passed to David, a short and unassuming shepherd-boy turned lyre-player in the court of Saul who humbly defeats the giant philistine warrior, Goliath, in battle. David’s heroism lies in his meekness and humility, but all the credit goes to God, as the Biblical narrator indicates. After the fall of Saul, David assumes power. He marries Saul’s daughter, Michal, a refined lady of high society who is ashamed of David’s wanton musical ways –especially his erratic dancing in a loin cloth after the conclusion of battle. David is notable because he is a craftsman, a musician, and a creator like Cain (David is traditionally held to be the writer of the Psalms) and thus he is a privately selfish person but a publicly righteous leader. He is complex and flawed, as in the infamous case of his lust for Bathsheba. David is famed throughout the world because of his self-centered nature –he is a humble, warrior, poet king who also represents the height of political and cultural flourishing in the Bible. He is the king par excellence that all future kings of Israel are compared to, including the fabled Messiah, or the divinely anointed king of all peoples.

David and Bathsheba have a son named Solomon who longs for wisdom above all else. He is a writer, like his father. Traditionally, Solomon writes the Proverbs, Song of Songs, and Ecclesiastes. He begins with a series of wisdom quotations, followed by the book of deep love, and lastly, his thinking leads him to become morbid and even, at times, a fatalistic man. Perhaps approaching quasi-philosopher, the wise Solomon is nevertheless overshadowed by his father, the poet king, David.

Following David and Solomon, the leaders of Israel grow increasingly decadent until the nation is once again enslaved, this time by the Babylonians. Between enslavement and a decline in the old order, many Israelite prophets call for a messiah, or a savior-king to restore the order of David, such as a tolerant leader like Cyrus of Persia. Later, in the Christian scriptures, this messiah will be identified as Jesus. However, Jesus is apparently borne for political rule (recall Jesus’s encounter with the devil who tempts him with ultimate political power in exchange for devil-worship). Instead, Jesus gathers a group of followers and performs a variety of miracles, but only when he summons a large enough crowd does he deliver his famous ‘Sermon on the Mount’ –in which Jesus spells out his vision of the right way of life in the Beatitudes (or eight “blessed are the…” rather than “thou shalt…”). It is an extraordinary moment wherein all hitherto values are re-evaluated. Jesus intensifies Mosaic law by commanding the fullest extent of moral purity, the criteria for which few ‘Old Testament’ figures would ever meet. All pride is condemned, and surrendering to evildoers is praised –it brings to mind the definition of justice offered by Polemarchos in Book I of Plato’s Republic in which the distinction between friends and enemies is central to the just city/man. At any rate, Jesus erases this distinction and suggests prayer for enemies, and instructs the new purified people to turn the other cheek to abusers and so on. He reorients the Mosaic idea of neighborliness into a universalist idea of love (i.e. the parable of the Good Samaritan). People are not only encouraged to love another, but now they are commanded to love (Paul reiterates the primacy of Christian love: ‘faith, hope, love abide: but the greatest of these is love.’)

Because of his large following of people, many of whom are drawn to miracles, Jesus draws the ire of the Pharisees and other traditional Jewish authorities. They are resentful of his popularity. They press Judean ruler, Pontius Pilate, to condemn Jesus to death under Roman blasphemy laws. Thus, Jesus’s gruesome death by crucifixion on a barren heath, known as the “place of the skull,” becomes a symbol of redemption for all humans, and the possibility of eternal life (as was once offered in the Garden of Eden). Classical heroism is replaced by modern martyrdom. Jesus’s offer of eternal life is further buttressed by his corporeal resurrection from death. He appears to his apostles with varying claims about the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit –opening the door for future theologians to puzzle over the nature and existence of a trinitarian God who is no longer a single god for one particular chosen people. Therefore, the new scriptures claim to be the fulfillment of the Jewish Biblical saga. In Acts, a council is gathered to determine which parts of Mosaic law will be upheld, such as circumcision (which is no longer a held to be a divine requirement). And rather than signs and symbols of a covenant between God and Man, the apostle Paul zealously argues that belief in Jesus alone is the new criteria for the faith which supersedes Mosaic law. In the wake of this grand upheaval, distinctions are removed between friends and enemies, slaves and freemen, men and women, and so on. Regarding private property, for early Christians most every personal possession was held in common, from each according to his need.

However, Jesus’s teaching raises more questions than it answers: how are redeemed Christians to live in an unredeemed world? What does it mean to give unto Caesar what belongs to him? What exactly is the property of Caesar? How are Christians intended to act in accord with virtue as both earthly citizens as well as patient pilgrims waiting for an apocalyptic conclusion? Paul and Peter attempt to answer these questions to an extent, however the incomplete nature of the scriptures forces these and many other problematic questions to be addressed by future Christian theologians, like St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas, who both attempt to make Christian comport with the classical tradition of Plato and Aristotle.


This essay was heavily influenced by Thomas Pangle and Timothy Burns and their writings on “Biblical Political Theology” in their book The Key Texts of Political Philosophy.

Notes on the Samia

The Samia, or the “Girl From Samos,” is the second most complete play that has come down to us from Menander’s collection of comedies (the Samia has 132 lines missing, while Dyskolos has 39). The Samia was recovered with the “Cairo Codex” in 1907 along with other fragments of Menander comedies (“Men at Arbitration” and “She Who Was Sheared”) and other portions of the Samia were recovered in other papyri.

The plot of the Samia follows a characteristically laughable storyline: an accident happens, and the characters attempt to conceal the truth, only for the secret to cause greater confusion and consternation among the characters.

The comedy takes place within the city of Athens. A rich Athenian named Demeas lives next door to a poor man, Nikeratos. Demeas has an adopted son named Moschion, and Nikeratos has a daughter named Plangon. Moschion delivers a soliloquy to the set the scene at the outset of the play. He tells of a drama in which he had ‘accidentally’ violated Plangon in a confusing situation, she gave birth to a child and then gave it away to Chrysis (his father, Demeas’s concubine) to care for. Both of their fathers have been away are returning from a trip to Pontos (south of Athens) soon. Upon their return, it is jointly decided that Demeas will marry Plangon. As the play progresses (with certain fragments missing) Demeas discovers (by overhearing from Moschion’s nurse) that Chrysis’s child is in fact the offspring of Moschion. Demeas believes his son has been seduced by Chrysis so he sends her away – she is taken in by Demeas’s neighbor, Nikeratos. Eventually, Moschion reveals the truth to his father, Demeas, and after a series of chaotic situations, Moschion and Nikeratos find common ground, and the play ends with Moschion marrying Plangon.

Notably, Menander’s plays (so-called “New Comedy”) are remarkably distinct from Aristophanes’s comedies. Menander’s plays are lighter, sillier, social satires of ridiculous situations. They are amusing, but they lack the depth of the Aristophanean comedies. The following is a 4th century mosaic depicting the events of Act IV of Menander’s Samia:

File:Samia (Girl from Samos) Mytilene 3cAD.jpg

For this reading I used the late Maurice Balme’s translation.

Who Is Heraclitus?

As far as we know, Heraclitus and Parmenides were contemporaries: Heraclitus was from Asia Minor, and Parmenides was from Southern Italy. We think Heraclitus remained in his hometown of Ephesus all his life. He lived perhaps sometime around 500 BC.

According to the popular Western imagination, Heraclitus is often portrayed as a weeping, brooding philosopher. In Raphael’s famous “School in Athens” Heraclitus is shown off-center, in the corner and alone, while every other thinker is engaged in communication.

According to Eva Brann, in her book Logos, Heraclitus’s teaching is unique among the pre-Socratic philosophers. He believes the world can be explained by means of the logos – explanation, reason, mathematics, or “rationality” (the Latin translation) which is the principle of exchange. The world behaves, or perhaps can merely be explained, by means of laws. There is regularity to the chaos. That regularity is identified as a playful ‘cosmic fire.’ Heraclitus compares the fundamental element of the world to “fire” (many latter historians of philosophy have interpreted this comparison literally, a la Bertrand Russell’s naive materialism in The History of Western Philosophy). Aristotle includes Heraclitus among the physikoi -the investigators of the physical world. The Heraclitean fire is like a transformative substance, the well-spring of a certain ordered chaos to the cosmos.

In addition, Nietzsche provides some unfinished notes on five Greek philosophers in Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks in 1873. In it, he describes Heraclitus’s philosophy as a kind of Kantian intuitive thinking which perceives the world of opposites (i.e. all objects exist in relation to one another) but that they each emerge out of one continuous action, or strife. All things come to be, temporarily, and then pass into cosmic fire. Heraclitus represents the harmony of two seeming antinomies: law and flux. All that remains of Heraclitus’s thinking is 131 mysterious aphorisms captured in various texts. From what we can gather from his surviving texts, “Becoming” not “being,” takes precedence in Heraclitus -he denies any fixed, immutable “being” (Nietzsche paraphrases Heraclitus’s famous maxim as: “You use names for things as though they rigidly, persistently endured; yet even the stream into which you step a second time is not the one you stepped into before”). The logos post Heraclitus has had a memorable career throughout Western thought: from Plato, to the Bible (particularly in the Gospel According to John) and Plotinus, and through Nietzsche.